Another article I couldn't sell.
On Griswold,
Santorum is Right—And Wrong
Senator
Santorum has managed to become a lightning rod for criticism for his
argument that Griswold v. Connecticut (1965) was wrongly decided. I am sure that for the vast majority of
Americans, the notion of overturning Griswold
seems like the heights of madness.
Not just libertarians, but even nearly all conservatives, would regard
state laws that banned married couples from
obtaining contraceptives, as positively bizarre. (And even Senator
Santorum thinks such laws would be bad ideas.)
First of all, let’s distinguish
between public policy and constitutionality.
Not every law that is constitutional is necessarily a good idea. The Militia Act
of 1792 required every white male citizen between 18 and 45 to own a gun. If Congress passed such a law today, it would
certainly be constitutional, but perhaps not wise. Limitations on government power that the
Framers found compelling in 1789 sometimes
seem less persuasive today.
The idea of states telling married couples that they could not
obtain contraceptives seems pretty ridiculous today, but that alone does not
make such a law unconstitutional. If you
believe that government derives its authority from the consent of the governed,
it is very easy to hold, as Justice Stewart’s dissenting opinion in Griswold does, that this was “an
uncommonly silly law” but still constitutional.
It is also hard to imagine that any
state today would pass such a law, even if the Supreme Court overturned Griswold.
You may be wondering, “Why is
Santorum so upset with Griswold? Does he really want contraception made into a
crime?” I can tell you why many people,
myself included, regard Griswold as a
terrible jurisprudential mistake. I have
concluded, as a result of a bit of study of the history of contraception laws
in the United States, that Griswold came
to the right conclusion (such laws are unconstitutional), but by a terribly
incorrect process. In so doing, it
created a precedent that later decisions used to reach often wrong conclusions.
For almost two thousand years,
contraception was regarded with considerable skepticism by Christianity,
because it was associated with pagan culture (along with abortion,
homosexuality, prostitution, and adult men marrying girls as young as 12). To my surprise, however, when I started
digging through both primary
and secondary
sources, I was unable to find any laws
in America prohibiting contraceptives until the 1873
Comstock Act, which classified contraceptive devices and information as
obscenity.
The Ninth Amendment guarantees
that, “The
enumeration in the Constitution, of certain rights, shall not be construed to
deny or disparage others retained by the people.” If there had been state or federal laws in
1791 prohibiting contraceptives, when the states ratified the Ninth Amendment,
you could argue that contraception was not a right “retained by the
people.” But there do not appear to be
any such laws. Griswold could easily, based on this lack of such laws, have made
an originalist argument that Connecticut’s law violated the Ninth
Amendment.
The problem was that Justice
William O. Douglas essentially admitted that the Supreme Court, for decades,
had abandoned anything that was recognizably originalism. Douglas’s opinion listing multiple rights
that the Court had found that were not explicitly mentioned in the
Constitution, but that “specific guarantees in the Bill of Rights have
penumbras, formed by emanations from those guarantees that help give them life
and substance.” Penumbras? Emanations?
If this sounds like doubletalk to you—I agree. Somehow, Justice Douglas concluded that there
was a right to privacy in there…somewhere.
Justice Goldberg’s concurring
opinion, engaged in the same type of doubletalk, asserting that the Ninth
Amendment protected rights that are “basic and fundamental and so deep-rooted
in our society” without ever identifying a method for identifying how you
determine that rights are “basic” or “fundamental” or “deep-rooted.” Yet Goldberg also claimed that just because
Connecticut’s law was unconstitutional, other laws did not run afoul of that
right to privacy. What laws? Laws that prohibit adultery, fornication, and
homosexuality.
If someone had slapped a condom
on Griswold, it would not matter that
Douglas reached the right conclusion by the wrong method. But Griswold
had progeny. The nebulous “right to
privacy” soon led to Roe v. Wade (1973) which again, reached almost the correct constitutional result, but again by the wrong
method. Abortion
after the unborn child began to stir was a crime under English law when the
states ratified the Constitution; if any procedure or “potion” caused the
unborn child to be born, and then die, that was murder. It is hard to imagine how partial-birth
abortions would qualify as constitutionally protected by this standard, but abortions in the first trimester certainly would be, as repugnant as they are.
Lawrence v. Texas (2003) was even more far afield on the privacy
question. Unlike Griswold, which came to the right result by the wrong method, and Roe, which came close to the right result by the wrong method, Lawrence built on that mythical right to privacy to find a
constitutional right to something that was felonious
(often capital felony) everywhere in America in 1791, and remained felonious
into the twentieth century.
Our Constitution is not a
straightjacket. We are not obligated to
keep our laws as museum pieces, forever stuck in 1791. Congress and the state legislatures, as the
representatives of the people, may modify and adjust laws to reflect changing
attitudes and values. But Griswold’s “right to privacy” has become
a tool for overturning majority will where no originalist meaning can fairly
justify the results.
Senator Santorum is wrong about Griswold. It came to the right conclusion. But Santorum is also right about Griswold: it comes to its conclusions
inaccurately, and the precedents based on it are frequently wrong.
Thank you for your post. Griswold and Roe are the present day philosophical source of the abortion machine. This loss of innocent life is offensive in the extreme. Thanks for your insight on the contortions needed to produce the wierd case law. We literally are paying a heavy spiritual, emotional, demographic and financial price for Gloria Steinem's "sine qua non."
ReplyDeleteYou should add Eisenstadt v. Baird. It held that unmarried persons had a right to contraception (well, that such laws violated equal protection).
ReplyDeleteSee how the ratchet works? Restrictions on contraception for married people are unconstitutional. So therefore you cannot deny contraception to unmarried persons because you are now treating married and unmarried people differently.